Intuition is one kind of mysticism common in the USA in our
time. Becoming familiar with intuition may help to arm
advocates of reason for the long war ahead.
OVERVIEW OF THE SERIES ON INTUITION. The
first post in this series on intuition was a book review (June 5, 2012) of The Good
in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value, by
philosophy professor Robert Audi.
(Unless specified otherwise, page citations below refer to Audi's book.) That first
post introduced the idea of intuition as it has been used by some academics
working in the field of ethics, as a branch of philosophy. For cultural contrast,
a later post, the third in the series, will present the idea of intuition
advocated not by an academic but by an author who writes to a mass audience.
This post, the second in the series, further considers the
academic concept of intuition and distinguishes it from
intuitionism, which is a theory of intuition -- describing not
only what an individual intuition is, but the manner in which individual
intuitions relate to each other and to other ideas. The source for this post is
Audi's The Good in the Right. This post will cite the views
of intuition that Audi, partly a rationalist, has originated or has adopted
from earlier intuitionists such as W. D. Ross, an empiricist.
Readers of this post should keep in mind its limitations: (1)
The brief notes here are my simplified interpretation of one academic's complex
presentation. (2) Academics who advocate intuitionism disagree with each other
on many aspects of intuitionism. (3) Academics are only one set of voices
speaking in favor of intuition in our culture today. Thus, this post is a
sampling.
WHAT IS AN INTUITION? Consider an example
of an intuition in the field of ethics. You see a man beating a child with a
belt. A thought -- "Beating a child is wrong!" -- appears in your mind.
That thought is the product of an intuition. (p. 60) In this case, the thought
is a narrow principle, where "principle" means an idea upon which
other ideas can stand. (For example, a broader abstraction -- such as the
generalization, "Harming others is wrong" -- could stand on multiple
narrow principles such as "Beating a child is wrong," "Hurting a
parent is wrong," and "Injuring a spouse is wrong.")
The intuitional sequence is simple. You look at a particular
social situation, and a thought appears in your mind. (p. 60) In epistemology,
this sequence is an instance of epistemological "realism," the view
that things outside the mind directly give rise to ideas in the mind.[1] More
technically, the "natural properties" of things (the "is"
of a child and a belt) somehow give rise to the "moral properties"
(the "ought"); and the moral properties -- received by the mind's
"moral sensitivity" (pp. 57 and 58) directly produce a narrow moral
principle in your mind: "Beating a child is wrong." This sequence is
a "reliable belief-generating process" (p. 57). Apparently this is
the manner in which intuitionists bridge the "is-ought"
gap.
DEFINITION. An intuition is a
"non-inferential cognition" (p. 8). An intuition, as a product of a
"process" that has no steps, is a proposition, that is, a statement,
a sentence. An intuition is not an individual concept. (p. 9) An example intuition,
from the field of ethics, is this proposition: "Everyone has a duty to
keep promises" (p. 43 for the duty of promise-keeping).
REQUIREMENTS. Not every thought that pops into the mind can
qualify as an intuition. "One may not ... simply insist that someone has a
[moral] duty, or ought to do something, and claim that one 'just sees' it. ... The intuitionist thesis that some
knowledge of what we ought to do is intuitive and non-inferential implies
neither that it is not reflective nor that it cannot be supported by argument
or refuted by relevant consideration to the contrary," Audi says (pp. 38-39).
Intuited knowledge might be supported by or reached independently by
"reflection," that is, thinking about the subject and making
inferences from other, already acquired knowledge.
For an intuition to actually be an intuition, it must have
these characteristics: (1) directness -- an intuition cannot
be based on a premise; (2) firmness
-- the intuitionist has a "definite sense that the proposition ... holds [true]"; (3) comprehensiblity -- an intuition must be
understandable by appropriately prepared, intelligent observers; and (4) pretheoreticality
-- forming or understanding intuitions comes directly from observation and
therefore cannot depend on a theory, which is a broad abstraction induced step
by step from evidence. (pp. 33-35)
FALLIBILITY. While "firmness" of belief is one
characteristic of an intuition, as Audi presents it, he and some other
intuitionists do not claim that intuitions are infallible. Intuitions can be
mistaken. Audi offers (pp. 8, 9) this analogy: Scientists rely on
sense-perceptions of the world as starting points for their scientific conclusions.
Scientists know, however, that sense-perceptions -- or our initial
understanding of them -- can be mistaken. Seeing a "bent" stick in a
pail of water is an example. The same idea, Audi says (p. 8), holds for
intuitions. Misunderstanding the facts of a situation can lead to a false
intuition -- but it is still an intuition. An intuition can never lead to a
false proposition as a result of a defective process of intuition. The reason
is that intuition is not a process. There are no steps in any particular intuition.
You look and the proposition appears in your mind.
If that is the nature of any particular intuition that
arises in observing a moral situation, then in what way do intuitions, once
acquired, relate to other knowledge?
WHAT IS INTUITIONISM? The term
"intuitionism" names a certain philosophical view, the conviction
that intuitions in some form play some role in creating knowledge. At least
among some academics, intuitionism is a theory that explains the source of
intuitions, the limits of intuitions, and the relationship of intuitions to
other elements of knowledge. Intuitionists disagree with each other about the
details.
EXAMPLE: AUDI'S INTUITIONISM. In the field of ethics,
intuitionism is "the view that at least some basic moral truths are
non-inferentially known" (p. 5). The theory of intuitionism described by
Audi has three characteristics. (pp. 20, 21, and 40)
First, Audi's intuitionism is pluralistic, which means that
the foundation of this ethics is made of a set of narrow, individual moral
"principles," like tiles in a floor. In contrast, in other ethical
theories, a single broad principle -- such as the Golden Rule or the
Categorical Imperative -- serves as a foundation (or sky hook) from which
narrower ethical guidelines can be deduced.
Second, each particular, narrow moral "principle"
(such as "Keep your promises") is "grounded" in one of these three sources: (a) an observable action (such as making a promise); (b) an item of
knowledge (a bleeding man will die); or (c) an accessible fact (such as the fact that one individual can benefit others).
Third, each narrow, intuited "principle" is
"knowable by ordinary moral agents," that is, individuals who are
concerned about acting properly.
Audi is a syncretist. He weaves together elements from
various sources into one intuitionist theory of ethics. For example, he melds (1)
the idea of a set of intuited moral principles (the narrow kind) such as
"Keep promises" and "Do no harm to others," with (2)
Immanuel Kant's overarching moral rule of the categorical
imperative.
TYPES OF INTUITIONISM. There are various theories of
intuitionist ethics (and ethics is only one field in which intuitionists work).
Some are rationalistic; others are empiricist; and still others (such as
Audi's) are a combination of the two. (pp. 2 and 19) Some forms of intuitionism
are "contextualist," that is, the intuitions are grounded in the
context of a moral situation and arise automatically without inference and
without reflection. (p. 59) Some forms of intuitionism are radical; their advocates accept
only the intuitions themselves as guides and reject any form of reasoning about
them. Other forms of intuitionism are moderate, as with Audi's theory, in which
intuitions provide elements of the moral theory but "reasoning"
weaves them into wider generalizations or at least connects them with an
overarching principle such as the categorical imperative. (pp. 6 and 54)
CONCLUSIONS. On many issues,
intuitionists in academia disagree among themselves, but they agree that
intuition -- a claim to immediate cognition, from whatever source -- plays or
should play some role in our knowledge of what we should do in the world. These
intuitionists are commanding a seldom-seen but powerful battalion of soldiers
in the war of mysticism against reason.
Burgess Laughlin
Author, The Power and the Glory: The Key Ideas and
Crusading Lives of Eight Debaters of Reason vs. Faith, at http://www.reasonversusmysticism.com